a2zpsychology.com > Psychology Guide > Theories > Gestalt Theory |
GESTALT
THEORY
by
Max Wertheimer (1924)
[an address before the
Kant Society, Berlin, '7th December, 1924], Erlangen, 1925.
In the translation by Willis D. Ellis published in his "Source
Book of Gestalt Psychology,"
New York: Harcourt, Brace and Co, 1938.
|
What is Gestalt theory and what does it intend?
Gestalt theory was the outcome of concrete investigations in psychology,
logic, and epistemology. The prevailing situation at the time of its origin
may be briefly sketched as follows. We go from the world of everyday events to
that of science, and not unnaturally assume that in making this transition we
shall gain a deeper and more precise understanding of essentials. The
transition should mark an advance. And yet, though one may have learned a
great deal, one is poorer than before. It is the same in psychology. Here too
we find science intent upon a systematic collection of data, yet often
excluding through that very activity precisely that which is most vivid and
real in the living phenomena it studies. Somehow the thing that matters has
eluded us. What happens when a problem is solved, when one
suddenly "sees the point"? Common as this experience is, we seek in
vain for it in the textbooks of psychology. Of things arid, poor, and
inessential there is an abundance, but that which really matters is missing.
Instead we are told of formation of concepts, of abstraction and
generalization, of class concepts and judgments, perhaps of associations,
creative phantasy, intuitions, talents - anything but an answer to our
original problem. And what are these last words but names for the problem?
Where are the penetrating answers? Psychology is replete with terms of great
potentiality - personality, essence, intuition, and the rest. But when one
seeks to grasp their concrete content, such terms fail. This is the situation and it is characteristic of
modern science that the same problem should appear everywhere. Several
attempts have been made to remedy the matter. One was a frank defeatism
preaching the severance of science and life: there are regions which are
inaccessible to science. Other theories established a sharp distinction
between the natural and moral sciences: the exactitude and precision of
chemistry and physics are characteristic of natural science, but
"scientific" accuracy has no place in a study of the mind and its
ways. This must be renounced in favour of other categories. Without pausing for further examples, let us consider
rather a question naturally underlying the whole discussion: Is
"science" really the kind of thing we have implied? The word science
has often suggested a certain outlook, certain fundamental assumptions,
certain procedures and attitudes - but do these imply that this is the only
possibility of scientific method? Perhaps science already embodies methods
leading in an entirely different direction, methods which have been
continually stifled by the seemingly necessary, dominant ones. It is
conceivable, for instance, that a host of facts and problems have been
concealed rather than illuminated by the prevailing scientific tradition. Even
though the traditional methods of science are undoubtedly adequate in many
cases, there may be others where they lead us astray. Perhaps something in the
very nature of the traditional outlook may have led its exponents at times to
ignore precisely that which is truly essential. Gestalt theory will not be satisfied with sham
solutions suggested by a simple dichotomy of science and life. Instead,
Gestalt theory is resolved to penetrate the problem itself by examining the
fundamental assumptions of science. It has long seemed obvious - and is, in
fact, the characteristic tone of European science - that "science"
means breaking up complexes into their component elements. Isolate the
elements, discover their laws, then reassemble them, and the problem is
solved. All wholes are reduced to pieces and piecewise relations between
pieces. The fundamental "formula" of Gestalt theory
might be expressed in this way. There are wholes, the behaviour of which is
not determined by that of their individual elements, but where the
part-processes are themselves determined by the intrinsic nature of the whole.
It is the hope of Gestalt theory to determine the nature of such wholes. With a formula such as this one might close, for
Gestalt theory is neither more nor less than this. It is not interested in
puzzling out philosophic questions which such a formula might suggest. Gestalt theory has to do with concrete research; it
is not only an outcome but a device : not only a theory about results but a
means toward further discoveries. This is not merely the proposal of one or
more problems but an attempt to see what is really taking place in science.
This problem cannot be solved by listing possibilities for systematization,
classification, and arrangement. If it is to be attacked at all, we must be
guided by the spirit of the new method and by the concrete nature of the
things themselves which we are studying, and set ourselves to penetrate to
that which is really given by nature. There is another difficulty that may be illustrated
by the following example. Suppose a mathematician shows you a proposition and
you begin to "classify" it. This proposition, you say, is of such
and such type, belongs in this or that historical category, and so on. Is that
how the mathematician works? "Why, you haven't grasped the thing at
all," the mathematician will exclaim. "See here, this formula is not
an independent, closed fact that can be dealt with for itself alone. You must
see its dynamic functional relationship to the whole from which it was lifted
or you will never understand it." What holds for the mathematical formula applies also
to the "formula" of Gestalt theory. The attempt of Gestalt theory to
disclose the functional meaning of its own formula is no less strict than is
the mathematician's. The attempt to explain Gestalt theory in a short essay is
the more difficult because of the terms which are used: part, whole, intrinsic
determination. All of them have in the past been the topic of endless
discussions where each disputant has understood them differently. And even
worse has been the cataloguing attitude adopted toward them. What they lacked
has been actual research. Like many another "philosophic" problem
they have been withheld from contact with reality and scientific work. About all I can hope for in so short a discussion is
to suggest a few of the problems which at present occupy the attention of
Gestalt theory and something of the way they are being attacked. To repeat: the problem has not merely to do with
scientific work - it is a fundamental problem of our times. Gestalt theory is
not something suddenly and unexpectedly dropped upon us from above; it is,
rather, a palpable convergence of problems ranging throughout the sciences and
the various philosophic standpoints of modern times. Let us take, for example, an event in the history of
psychology. One turned from a living experience to science and
asked what it had to say about this experience, and one found an assortment of
elements, sensational images, feelings, acts of will and laws governing these
elements - and was told, "Take your choice, reconstruct from them the
experience you had." Such procedure led to difficulties in concrete
psychological research and to the emergence of problems which defied solution
by traditional analytic methods. Historically the most important impulse came
from v. Ehrenfels who raised the following problem. Psychology had said that
experience is a compound of elements: we hear a melody and then, upon hearing
it again, memory enables us to recognize it. But what is it that enables us to
recognize the melody when it is played in a new key? The sum of the elements
is different, yet the melody is the same; indeed, one is often not even aware
that a transposition has been made. When in retrospect we consider the prevailing
situation we are struck by two aspects of v. Ehrenfels's thesis; on the one
hand one is surprised at the essentially summative character of his theory, on
the other one admires his courage in propounding and defending his
proposition. Strictlv interpreted, v. Ehrenfels's position was this: I play a
familiar melody of six tones and employ six new tones, yet you recognize the
melody despite the change. There must be a something more than the sum of six
tones, viz. a seventh something, which is the form-quality, the Gestaltqualität,
of the original six. It is this seventh factor or element which enabled you to
recognize the melody despite its transposition. Another type of explanation, also designed to bolster
the elementaristic hypothesis, was that to this total of six or more tones
there come certain "higher processes" which operate upon the given
material to "produce" unity. This was the situation until Gestalt theory raised
the radical question: Is it really true that when I hear a melody I have a sum
of individual tones (pieces) which constitute the primary foundation of my
experience? Is not perhaps the reverse of this true? What I really have, what
I hear of each individual note, what I experience at each place in the melody
is apart which is itself determined by the character of the whole. What is
given me by the melody does not arise (through the agency of any auxiliary
factor) as a secondary process from the sum of the pieces as such. Instead,
what takes place in each single part already depends upon what the whole is.
The flesh and blood of a tone depends from the start upon its role in the
melody: a b as leading tone to c is something radically different from the b
as tonic. It belongs to the flesh and blood of the things given in experience
[Gegebenheiten], how, in what role, in what function they are in their whole. Let us leave the melody example and turn to another
field. Take the case of threshold phenomena. It has long been held that a
certain stimulus necessarily produces a certain sensation. Thus, when two
stimuli are sufficiently different, the sensations also will be different.
Psychology is filled with careful inquiries regarding threshold phenomena. To
account for the difficulties constantly being encountered it was assumed that
these phenomena must be influenced by higher mental functions, judgments,
illusions, attention, etc. And this continued until the radical question was
raised : Is it really true that a specific stimulus always gives rise to the
same sensation? Perhaps the prevailing. whole-conditions will themselves
determine the effect of stimulation? This kind of formulation leads to
experimentation, and experiments show, for example, that when I see two
colours the sensations I have are determined by the whole-conditions of the
entire stimulus situation. Thus, also, the same local physical stimulus
pattern can give rise to either a unitary and homogeneous figure, or to an
articulated figure with different parts, all depending upon the
whole-conditions which may favour either unity or articulation. Obviously the
task, then, is to investigate these "whole-conditions" and discover
what influences they exert upon experience. Advancing another step we come to the question
whether perhaps any part depends upon the particular whole in which it occurs.
Experiments, largely on vision, have answered this question in the
affirmative. Among other things they demand that the traditional theory of
visual contrast be replaced by a theory which takes account of whole-part
conditions. Our next point is that my field comprises also my
Ego. There is not from the beginning an Ego over-against others, but the
genesis of an Ego offers one of the most fascinating problems, the solution of
which seems to lie in Gestalt principles. However, once constituted, the Ego
is a functional part of the total field. Proceeding as before we may therefore
ask: What happens to the Ego as a part of the field? Is the resulting
behaviour the piecewise sort of thing associationism, experience theory, and
the like, would have us believe? Experimental results contradict this
interpretation and again we often find that the laws of whole-processes
operative in such a field tend toward a "meaningful" behaviour of
its parts. This field is not a summation of sense data and no
description of it which considers such separate pieces to be primary will be
correct. If it were, then for children, primitive peoples and animals
experience would be nothing but piece-sensations. The next most developed
creatures would have, in addition to independent sensations, something higher,
and so on. But this whole picture is the opposite of what actual inquiry has
disclosed. We have learned to recognize the "sensations" of our
textbooks as products of a late culture utterly different from the experiences
of more primitive stages. Who experiences the sensation of a specific red in
that sense? What the man of the streets, children, or primitive men normally
react to is something coloured but at the same time exciting, gay, strong, or
affecting - not "sensations". The programme to treat the organism as a part in a
larger field necessitates the reformulation of the problem as to the relation
between organism and environment. The stimulus-sensation connection must be
replaced by a connection between alteration in the field conditions, the vital
situation, and the total reaction of the organism by a change in its attitude,
striving, and feeling. There is, however, another step to be considered. A man is not only a part of his field, he is also one among other men. When a group of people work together it rarely occurs, and then only under very special conditions, that they constitute a mere-sum of independent Egos. Instead the common enterprise often becomes their mutual concern and each works as a meaningfully functioning part of the whole. Consider a group of South Sea Islanders engaged in some community occupation, or a group of children playing together. Only under very special circumstances does an "I" stand out alone. Then the balance which obtained during harmonious and systematic occupation may be upset and give way to a surrogate (under certain conditions, pathological) new balance.
Further discussion of this point would carry us into
the work of social and cultural science which cannot be followed here. Instead
let us consider certain other illustrations. What was said above of stimulus
and sensation is applicable to physiology and the biological sciences no less
than to psychology. It has been tried, for example, by postulating sums of
more and more special apparatus, to account for meaningful or, as it is often
called, purposive behaviour. Once more we find meaninglessly combined reflexes
taken for granted although it is probable that even with minute organisms it
is not true that a piece-stimulus automatically bring about its corresponding
piece-effect. Opposing this view is vitalism which, however, as it
appears to Gestalt theory, also errs in its efforts to solve the problem, for
it, too, begins with the assumption that natural occurrences are themselves
essentially blind and haphazard - and adds a mystical something over and above
them which imposes order. Vitalism fails to inquire of physical events whether
a genuine order might not already prevail amongst them. And yet nature does
exhibit numerous instances of physical wholes in which part events are
determined by the inner structure of the whole. These brief references to biology will suffice to
remind us that whole-phenomena are not "merely" psychological, but
appear in other sciences as well. Obviously, therefore, the problem is not
solved by separating off various provinces of science and classifying
whole-phenomena as something peculiar to psychology. The fundamental question can be very simply stated:
Are the parts of a given whole determined by the inner structure of that
whole, or are the events such that, as independent, piecemeal, fortuitous and
blind the total activity is a sum of the part-activities? Human beings can, of
course, devise a kind of physics of their own - e.g. a sequence of machines -
exemplifying the latter half of our question, but this does not signify that
all natural phenomena are of this type. Here is a place where Gestalt theory
is least easily understood and this because of the great number of prejudices
about nature which have accumulated during the centuries. Nature is thought of
as something essentially blind in its laws, where whatever takes place in the
whole is purely a sum of individual occurrences. This view was the natural
result of the struggle which physics has always had to purge itself of
teleology. To-day it can be seen that we are obliged to traverse other routes
than those suggested by this kind of purposivism. Let us proceed another step and ask: How does all
this stand with regard to the problem of body and mind? What does my knowledge
of another's mental experiences amount to and how do I obtain it? There are,
of course, old and established dogmas on these points: The mental and physical
are wholly heterogeneous: There obtains between them an absolute dichotomy.
(From this point of departure philosophers have drawn an array of metaphysical
deductions so as to attribute all the good qualities to mind while reserving
for nature the odious.) As regards the second question, my discerning mental
phenomena in others is traditionally explained as inference by analogy.
Strictly interpreted the principle here is that something mental is
meaninglessly coupled with something physical. I observe the physical and
infer the mental from it more or less according to the following scheme: I see
someone press a button on the wall and infer that he wants the light to go on.
There may be couplings of this sort. However, many scientists have been
disturbed by this dualism.and have tried to save themselves by recourse to
very curious hypotheses. Indeed, the ordinary person would violently refuse to
believe that when he sees his companion startled, frightened, or angry he is
seeing only certain physical occurrences which themselves have nothing to do
(in their inner nature) with the mental, being only superficially coupled with
it: you have frequently seen this and this combined ... etc. There have been
many attempts to surmount this problem. One speaks, for example, of intuition
and says there can be no other possibility, for I see my companion's fear. It
is not true, argue the intuitionists, that I see only the bare bodily
activities meaninglessly coupled with other and invisible activities. However
inadmissible it may otherwise be, an intuition theory does have at least this
in its favour, it shows a suspicion that the traditional procedure might be
successfully reversed. But the word intuition is at best only a naming of that
which we must strive to lay hold of. This and other hypotheses, apprehended as they now
are, will not advance scientific pursuit, for science demands fruitful
penetration, not mere cataloguing and systematization. But the question is,
How does the matter really stand? Looking more closely we find a I third
assumption, namely that a process such as fear is a matter of consciousness.
Is this true? Suppose you see a person who is kindly or benevolent. Does
anyone suppose that this person is feeling mawkish? No one could possibly
believe that. The characteristic feature of such behaviour has very little to
do with consciousness. It has been one of the easiest contrivances of
philosophy to identify a man's real behaviour and the direction of his mind
with his consciousness. Parenthetically, in the opinion of many people the
distinction between idealism and materialism implies that between the noble
and the ignoble. Yet does one really mean by this to contrast consciousness
with the blithesome budding of trees? Indeed, what is there so repugnant about
the materialistic and mechanical? What is so attractive about the idealistic?
Does it come from the material qualities of the connected pieces? Broadly
speaking most psychological theories and textbooks, despite their continued
emphasis upon consciousness, are far more "materialistic", arid, and
spiritless than a living tree - which probably has no consciousness at all.
The point is not what the material pieces are, but what kind of whole it is.
Proceeding in terms of specific problems one soon realizes how many bodily
activities there are which give no hint of a separation between body and mind.
Imagine a dance, a dance full of grace and joy. What is the situation in such
a dance? Do we have a summation of physical limb movements and a psychical
consciousness? No. Obviously this answer does not solve the problem; we have
to start anew - and it seems to me that a proper and fruitful point of attack
has been discovered. One finds many processes which, in their dynamical form,
are identical regardless of variations in the material character of their
elements. When a man is timid, afraid or energetic, happy or sad, it can often
be shown that the course of his physical processes is Gestalt-identical with
the course pursued by the mental processes. Again In I can only indicate the direction of
thought. I have touched on the question of body and mind merely to show that
the problem we are discussing also has its philosophic aspects. To strengthen
the import of the foregoing suggestions let us consider the fields of
epistemology and logic. For centuries the assumption has prevailed that our
world is essentially a summation of elements. For Hume and largely also for
Kant the world is like a bundle of fragments, and the dogma of meaningless
summations continues to play its part. As for logic, it supplies: concepts,
which when rigorously viewed are but sums of properties; classes, which upon
closer inspection prove to be mere catchalls ; syllogisms, devised by
arbitrarily lumping together any two propositions having the character that
... etc. When one considers what a concept is in living thought, what it
really means to grasp a conclusion; when one considers what the crucial thing
is about a mathematical proof and the concrete interrelationships it involves,
one sees that the categories of traditional logic have accomplished nothing in
this direction. It is our task to inquire, whether a logic is
possible which is not piecemeal. Indeed the same question arises in
mathematics also. Is it necessary that all mathematics be established upon a
piecewise basis? What sort of mathematical system would it be in which this
were not the case? There have been attempts to answer the latter question but
almost always they have fallen back in the end upon the old procedures. This
fate has overtaken many, for the result of training in piecewise thinking is
extraordinarily tenacious. It is not enough and certainly does not constitute
a solution of the, principal problem if one shows that the atoms a of
mathematics are both piecemeal and t the same time evince something of the
opposite character. The problem has been scientifically grasped only when an
attack specifically designed to yield positive results has been launched. Just
how this attack is to be made seems to many mathematicians a colossal problem,
but perhaps the quantum theory will force the mathematicians to attack it. This brings us to the close of an attempt to present
a view of the problem as illustrated by its specific appearances in various
fields. In concluding I may suggest a certain unification of these
illustrations somewhat as follows. I consider the situation from the point of
view of a theory of aggregates and say: How should a world be where science,
concepts, inquiry, investigation, and comprehension of inner unities were
impossible? The answer is obvious. This world would be a manifold of disparate
pieces. Secondly, what kind of world would there have to be in which a
piecewise science would apply? The answer is again quite simple, for here one
needs only a system of recurrent couplings that are blind and piecewise in
character, whereupon everything is available for a pursuit of the traditional
piecewise methods of logic, mathematics, and science generally in so far as
these presuppose this kind of world. But there is a third kind of aggregate
which has been but cursorily investigated. These are the aggregates in which a
manifold is not compounded from adjacently situated pieces but rather such
that a term at its place in that aggregate is determined by the whole-laws of
the aggregate itself. Pictorially: suppose the world were a vast plateau
upon which were many musicians. I walk about listening and watching the
players. First suppose that the world is a meaningless plurality. Everyone
does as he will, each for himself. What happens together when I hear ten
players might be the basis for my guessing as to what they all are doing, but
this is merely a matter of chance and probability much as in the kinetics of
gas molecules. - A second possibility would be that each time one musician
played c, another played f so and so many seconds later. I work out a theory
of blind couplings but the playing as a whole remains meaningless. This is
what many people think physics does, but the real work of physics belies this.
- The third possibility is, say, a Beethoven symphony where it would be
possible for one to select one part of the whole and work from that towards an
idea of the structural principle motivating and determining the whole. Here
the fundamental laws are not those of fortuitous pieces, but concern the very
character of the event. Footnotes:
5]
See KÖHLER, W. (1938). Physical Gestalten. In: W. D. Ellis (Ed.), A Source
Book of Gestalt Psychology, 17-54. Reprint (1997): New York: The Gestalt
Journal Press. |